Skip to content
13.8

The key problem with the “brain in a vat” thought experiment

Even with the best technology imaginable, you’d probably never be able to exist as a consciously aware brain in a vat.
An image of a glass jar containing a brain on a textured background.
Wiki Commons / Jensflorian / Adobe Stock / Ivaylo / Big Think / Vincent Romero
Key Takeaways
  • The “brain in a vat” idea, often explored in science fiction, suggests that all human experience could be simulated through neural circuitry alone.
  • However, the brain in a vat (BIV) scenario seems to overlook the intricate interdependence between the brain and the body, suggesting that the brain cannot function in isolation but needs a biologically active system mirroring the complexities of an actual body.
  • Real-world interaction and bodily engagement may be essential for genuine experience and consciousness.

There is a certain kind of story about nature and our place in it that says all we experience, all we feel, is nothing but neural circuity. According to one thought experiment, if I were a smart enough doctor or computer scientist, I could put your brain in a vat, hook it up to a bunch of electrodes that enable some kind of simulation of the world, and you’d never know the difference. Fed the proper electrical stimulus, your brain would conjure up the exact same experiences as if you were wandering around in the world in your body. 

But is this “brain a vat” thought experiment right? Is direct experience — that most intimate and immediate sense of life and the world — really reducible to the wiring of neurons? The answer, I believe, is not at all. More importantly, the mistake at the heart of this idea is a primary example of the inability of certain philosophical perspectives on science to confront the centrality of human experience in doing science.

Reducing conscious experience

The thought experiment is prevalent in modern culture, inspiring numerous science-fiction films and TV shows, like The Matrix (so awesome) to Altered Carbon (very cool, but less awesome). It’s also the underpinning of much-talked-about ideas like the simulation hypothesis or Boltzmann Brains. Taken as a whole, brains in vats (let’s abbreviate them as BIVs) exemplify a particular metaphysics of science called reductionism, in which everything we experience can be reduced to the activity of lower levels in the hierarchies of structure in the physical world. Reductionism plays a big role in The Blind Spot: Why Science Cannot Ignore Human Experience, a new book Marcelo Glieser, Evan Thompson, and I have just published. In it, reductionism is seen as one of a constellation of views through which direct experience gets forgotten as that which makes scientific activity possible. The most dramatic feature of Blind Spot’s philosophy is when useful abstractions — extracted from scientific practice — are substituted as being more real than the rich, seamless life-world that is experienced. That’s exactly what happens with BIVs.

There are a number of ways to see how the BIV idea gets things wrong, but today I am going to draw from a lovely paper that my Blind Spot co-author Evan Thompson wrote with Diego Cosmelli. It’s called “Brain in a Vat or Body in a World? Brainbound versus Enactive Views of Experience.” Thompson and Cosmelli want us to take the BIV thought experiment seriously. What would it take to actually “envat” a brain? Any answer to this question — even one that assumes we had the best technology imaginable — must wrestle with a thorny problem: the fact that the brain and body are extremely interconnected, perhaps inextricably so.

Designing a BIV

Given that brains are just one organ in the collection of systems we call an organism, we would need to provide our brain with an apparatus that keeps it alive and functioning. Your brain would need to be constantly fed various substances at their exact concentrations — at the same frequency and in the same brain locations — to maintain healthy function. So, we would need a highly specific, highly resolved circulator system to deliver the required substances. Note, however, that these substances are not passively delivered: It is brain activity itself that determines where, when, and how the circulation system should carry out its task. This means our artificial circulatory system must be coupled at the highest resolution to the brain and its own activity in self-regulatory loops. As Thompson and Cosmelli put it: “Our life-sustaining system must support this intrinsic activity and respond to it locally and systemically at any given instant, independent of any outside evaluation of the brain’s needs.”

There is more, however. The brain as a living organ is not just maintained from the outside, or exogenously. The brain controls motor functions: how our body parts actually move, including our sense organs. So, instead of one-way control, there’s a continuous sensorimotor loop: endogenously controlled movement changes how the senses are stimulated, which gives rise to new movement. The brain has to deal not just with what is happening in the outside world but with what is happening as a result of its own intrinsic activity. This activity is highly nonlinear: It’s not a straightforward result of whatever the sensory inputs are, and it all has to be kept within viable limits so it doesn’t disrupt the homeostasis of the healthy, functioning brain.

Taking these and other requirements together, Thompson and Cosmelli conclude that to really envat a brain, you must embody it. Your vat would necessarily end up being a substitute body. Note that they aren’t claiming the substitute body has to be flesh and blood. Instead, they demonstrate how the BIV thought experiment undermines itself. Its fundamental idea is that neural circuitry is somehow the minimal condition/structure needed for experience. Instead, Thompson and Cosmelli demonstrate that being in a body that is itself active in the world is the minimal condition/structure necessary for experience. By beginning with the science of brains as living organs in living organisms, they demonstrate one way that the BIV idea undercuts its own logic. In other words, brains may be necessary for experience but they aren’t sufficient. They are one part of the holism that is embodiment in a world — the true “seat” of experience. 

“We’ve given reasons to think that the body and brain are so dynamically entangled in the causation and realization of consciousness as to be explanatorily inseparable,” write Thompson and Cosmelli.

To close, I want to note that these kinds of arguments are not just an academic philosophical game. There’s a steady drumbeat these days of people making powerful claims for AI. Some of these claims draw directly from philosophies animating the BIV argument. Understanding exactly where the flaws in that argument appear is one step to making sure we don’t end up building a deeply flawed society that rests exactly on those flaws.


Related

Up Next