Skip to content
Starts With A Bang

Hidden variable alternative to quantum spookiness fails

Do we actually live in a deterministic Universe, despite quantum physics? An alternative, non-spooky interpretation has now been ruled out.
spooky action quantum
The idea that two quanta could be instantaneously entangled with one another, even across large distances, is often talked about as the spookiest part of quantum physics. If reality were fundamentally deterministic and were governed by hidden variables, this spookiness could be removed. Unfortunately, attempts to do away with this type of quantum weirdness have all failed, as any experimental difference between the Copenhagen interpretation and hidden variable theories has only supported the standard picture of quantum mechanics.
Credit: Alan Stonebraker/American Physical Society
Key Takeaways
  • From Newton through Maxwell, every particle and interaction known seemed to obey a deterministic set of equations, but the discovery of radioactivity and quantum physics quickly changed all that.
  • In quantum physics, you can only predict the probability distribution of a set of possible outcomes, with an actual measurement required to tell you which outcome has actually occurred.
  • One interpretation of quantum physics, Bohmian mechanics, involves hidden variables and seeks to do away with quantum spookiness entirely. Its one measurable prediction just failed.
Sign up for the Starts With a Bang newsletter
Travel the universe with Dr. Ethan Siegel as he answers the biggest questions of all

For all of history, there’s been an underlying but unspoken assumption about the laws that govern the Universe: that if you know enough information about a system, like the positions, momenta, and properties of the particles within it, then you can use that information to predict precisely how that system will evolve and behave in the future. The assumption is, in other words, that the equations governing the Universe are deterministic. The classical equations of motion — Newton’s laws — are completely deterministic. The laws of gravity, both Newton’s and Einstein’s, are deterministic. Even Maxwell’s equations, governing classical electricity and magnetism, are 100% deterministic as well.

But that picture of the Universe got turned on its head with a series of discoveries that began in the late 1800s. Starting with radioactivity and radioactive decay, humanity slowly uncovered aspects about the nature of reality that were fundamentally quantum, casting doubt on the idea that we live in a deterministic Universe. In terms of predictive power, many aspects of reality could only be discussed in a statistical fashion: where a set of possible outcomes with appropriately weighted probabilities could be presented, but knowing which one would occur, and when, could not be established in advance of a measurement. The hope of avoiding the necessity of “quantum spookiness” was championed by many, including Einstein, with the most compelling alternative to determinism put forth by Louis de Broglie and David Bohm.

Decades later, Bohmian mechanics was finally put to a compelling experimental test, which — to the chagrin of many — it failed spectacularly. Here’s how the best alternative to the spooky nature of our quantum reality simply fails.

alice bob hidden variables
Quantum mechanics’ entangled pairs can be compared to a machine that throws out balls of opposite colors in opposite directions. When Bob catches a ball and sees that it is black, he immediately knows that Alice has caught a white one. In a theory that uses hidden variables, the balls had always contained hidden information about what color to show. However, quantum mechanics says that the balls were gray, or a combination of black and white, until someone looked at them, when one randomly turned white and the other black. Bell inequalities show that there are experiments that can differentiate between these cases. Such experiments have proven that quantum mechanics’ description is correct, and the balls have an indeterminate color until the measurement is made.
Credit: Johan Jamestad/The Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences

Is nature deterministic? There are all sorts of experiments we can perform that demonstrate that we cannot predictively know the outcomes of our quantum reality in any sort of definitive fashion.

  • Place a number of radioactive atoms in a container and wait a specific amount of time. When you observe your container at that later time, you can predict how many atoms remain versus how many have decayed, on average, and what the probability distribution will be of having a certain specific number of undecayed atoms remaining after a certain amount of time has elapsed. However, you cannot predict which atoms will decay versus which ones will remain, nor can you predict the exact number of atoms that will have decayed versus the ones that remain. Those latter aspects must be measured in order to be determined.
  • Fire a series of particles through a narrowly spaced double slit and you’ll be able to predict what sort of interference pattern will arise on the screen behind it, including the spacing and distribution of the areas of constructive and destructive interference. However, for each and every particle, even when you’re capable of sending them through the slits one at a time, you cannot predict — other than purely probabilistically — where each one is going to land. You must measure them, individually, in order to determine their outcomes.
  • Pass a series of particles (that possess quantum spin) through a magnetic field and you’ll observe that half of them deflect “up” and half “down,” aligned with or against the direction of the field. If you pass them through another magnet oriented the same way, the ones that went “up” will still go “up” and the ones that went “down” still go down, unless you pass them through an in-between magnet oriented in one of the two perpendicular directions. If you do, the beam will split again and the particles’ spins in the original direction will be re-randomized once again, with no way to determine which way they’ll split when you pass them through the final magnet. Again, you must measure each individual particle to determine what its outcome was.
spookiness
When a particle with quantum spin is passed through a directional magnet, it will split in at least 2 directions, dependent on spin orientation. If another magnet is set up in the same direction, no further split will ensue. However, if a third magnet is inserted between the two in a perpendicular direction, not only will the particles split in the new direction, but the information you had obtained about the original direction gets destroyed, leaving the particles to split again when they pass through the final magnet.
Credit: MJasK/Wikimedia Commons

The list of experiments that display this sort of quantum weirdness or spookiness is long, and examples such as the ones given are far from exhaustive. This inherently quantum behavior shows up in all sorts of physical systems, both for individual particles as well as for complex multi-particle systems, under a broad variety of conditions. Although physicists have been able to write down the rules and equations that govern these quantum systems, including the Pauli Exclusion Principle, the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle, the Schrödinger equation and many more, the fact is that only a set of possible conditions and probable outcomes can be predicted in the absence of a definitive measurement.

Somehow, in quantum systems, the act of making a measurement appears to be a very important factor, flying in the face of the idea that we inhabited a sort of “independent reality” that was agnostic about the role of the observer or the one doing the measuring. Properties of a physical system that had previously been treated as intrinsic and immutable — like position, momentum, angular momentum, or even the energy of a particle — were suddenly knowable only up to a certain precision. Moreover, the act of measuring those properties, which requires an interaction with another quantum of some type, fundamentally changes, or perhaps even determines, those values, while simultaneously increasing the indeterminism and/or uncertainties of other measurable parameters.

Although this explanation was and still is counterintuitive, it seems to be a requirement to accurately describe our Universe.

uncertainty heisenberg position momentum
This diagram illustrates the inherent uncertainty relation between position and momentum. When one is known more accurately, the other is inherently less able to be known accurately. Both position and momentum are better described by a probabilistic wavefunction than by a single value. Other pairs of conjugate variables, including energy and time, spin in two perpendicular directions, or angular position and angular momentum, also exhibit this same uncertainty relation.
Credit: Maschen/Wikimedia Commons

The central idea behind what we now call the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, which is the standard way that physics students are taught to conceive of the quantum Universe, is that nothing is certain until that critical moment where an observation occurs. Everything that cannot be exactly calculated from what’s already known is describable by some sort of wavefunction — a wave that encodes a continuum of more likely and less likely possible outcomes — until the critical moment when a measurement is made. At that precise instant, the wavefunction description gets replaced by a single, now-determined reality: what some describe as a collapse of the wavefunction. In other words:

  • every quantum in existence behaves as a wave while it propagates through a physical system,
  • but behaves as a particle when it interacts, or experiences an event, with an observer or a measurement apparatus.

If this sounds bizarre to you, as though it couldn’t possibly be right, don’t worry: you’re not alone in how you feel. It was this level of weirdness, or “spookiness,” that was so objectionable to many pioneers of the quantum Universe with Einstein himself being perhaps the most famous among them. Einstein was aghast at the idea that somehow reality was random in nature, and that effects could occur — like one member of a pair of identical atoms decaying while the other did not — without an identifiable cause. In many ways, this position was summed up in a famous remark attributed to Einstein, “God does not play dice with the Universe.” While Einstein himself never came up with a viable alternative to the Copenhagen interpretation, one of his (and Bohr’s) contemporaries had an idea for how reality could work instead: Louis de Broglie.

spookiness
The idea of a de Broglie wave is that every matter particle can also exhibit wavelike behavior, with the properties of the wave given by quantities like momentum and energy of the system. Everything, from electrons to human beings, behave like a wave under the proper conditions. The lower in momentum (i.e., the combination of velocity and mass) a particle is, the longer its de Broglie wavelength is.
Credit: Maschen/Wikimedia Commons

The idea that quanta could behave like waves began with light: first put forth by Huygens in the 1600s and then revived by Thomas Young’s double slit experiment at the dawn of the 19th century. Max Planck’s work a century later showed that light must indeed be quantized, however, and Einstein’s subsequent work on the photoelectric effect demonstrated light’s particle-like behavior as well. Just a few years later, Louis de Broglie gained fame for showing that it wasn’t simply light that possessed a dual nature of being simultaneously wave-like and particle-like, but that matter itself — and specifically, electrons — must possess a wave-like nature when subjected to the proper quantum conditions. His formula for calculating the wavelength of “matter waves” is still widely used today, and to de Broglie, it implied that the dual nature of quanta, both wave-like and matter-like, must be taken literally.

In de Broglie’s version of quantum physics, there were always concrete particles, with definite (but not always well-measured) positions to them, that are guided through space by these quantum mechanical wavefunctions, which he called “pilot waves.” Although de Broglie’s version of quantum physics couldn’t describe systems with more than one particle, and suffered from the challenge of not being able to measure or identify precisely what was “physical” about the pilot wave, it represented an interesting alternative to the Copenhagen interpretation: one where “pilot waves” guided particles through space, but that they always objectively existed as definitive particles, whose properties were then revealed by measurement.

Instead of being governed by the weird rules of quantum spookiness, de Broglie envisioned an underlying, hidden reality that was completely deterministic. Many of de Broglie’s ideas were expanded upon by other researchers, who all sought to discover a less “spooky” alternative to the quantum reality that generations of students, with no superior alternative, had been compelled to accept.

quantum tunneling
This generic illustration of quantum tunneling assumes there is a high, thin, but finite barrier separating a quantum wavefunction on one side of the x-axis from the other. While most of the wavefunction, and hence the probability of the field/particle that it’s a proxy for, reflects and remains on the original side, there is a finite, non-zero probability of tunneling through to the other side of the barrier. This phenomenon must be explicable in all interpretations of quantum mechanics.
Credit: Yuvalr/Wikimedia Commons

Perhaps the most famous extension came courtesy of the physicist David Bohm, working on similar problems a generation later. In the 1950s, Bohm developed his own interpretation of quantum physics that’s still considered today: the de Broglie-Bohm (or pilot wave) theory. The underlying wave equation, in this idea, is the same as the conventional Schrödinger equation, as in the Copenhagen interpretation. However, there’s also a guiding equation that acts on the wavefunction, and properties like the position of a particle can be extracted from the relationship of the Schrödinger equation’s wavefunction to that guiding equation. It’s an explicitly causal, deterministic interpretation of quantum mechanics, with the addition of a guiding equation to it.

Conceptually, however, it gives up something that the Copenhagen interpretation preserves: locality, or the idea that no information-carrying signal can be transmitted from one quantum to another at speeds exceeding the speed of light. Even if you accept non-locality, however, this pilot wave interpretation possesses its own difficulties. For one, you can’t recover classical dynamics using this pilot wave theory; Newton’s F = ma doesn’t describe the dynamics of a particle at all. In fact, the particle itself doesn’t affect the wavefunction in any way; rather, the wavefunction describes the velocity field of each particle or system of particles, and you have to apply the appropriate “guiding equation” to find out just where the particle is and how its motion is affected by whatever is exerting a force on it.

When a ball floats upon a river, its path will follow the river’s current, but its inertia will also determine its trajectory. As a result, it will normally take only a short amount of time before it winds up on one of the water’s banks: close to the shore. This is easily explicable with simple Newtonian mechanics.
Credit: byrev/pixabay

In many ways, pilot wave theory was more of an interesting counterexample to the assertion that “no hidden variable theory could reproduce the success of quantum indeterminism.” It could and in fact did, as Bohm’s pilot wave theory illustrated, although there was a cost: the theory demands both a fundamental non-locality and the difficult notion of having to extract physical properties from a guiding equation, whose results are not extractable in a straightforward fashion.

Consider the following example: a particle, like a ball, floating on top of a flowing river. In Newtonian mechanics, what happens to the ball is simple:

  • the ball has a mass,
  • which means it has an inertia,
  • and that means it follows Newton’s first and second laws.
  • This object in motion will remain in motion unless acted on by an outside force.
  • If it is acted upon by an outside force, it accelerates via Newton’s famous equation, F = ma.
  • As the ball travels downstream, the river’s twists and turns will cause the water to flow downstream, but will quickly drive the ball to one bank of the river or the other.

In Newton’s classical picture, the ball always winds up on one side of the river, and inertia is the guiding principle behind the floating ball’s net motion.

But in Bohmian mechanics, the flow of the river determines the evolution of the wavefunction, which should preferentially stay in the center of the river. This shows the conceptual difficulty with pilot wave theory: if you want your particle to ride on the wavefunction like a surfer — as de Broglie originally envisioned — you have to go through a variety of twisted contortions to get back the basic predictions that we’re all familiar with from classical mechanics. Bohmian mechanics does not lead one to recover Newtonian mechanics, even in the classical limit of the theory.

spookiness
One can envision an alternative to quantum weirdness or spookiness, where a quantum behaves in a wave-like fashion until you measure it, upon where it behaves like a particle. In the pilot wave interpretation, the particle is treated as similar to a “surfer” atop the “waves” that underlie the system. However, any interpretation making these claims must agree with all possible quantum physics experiments: a tall order.
Credit: Dan Harris/MIT

As the perfectly valid Copenhagen interpretation has long demonstrated, however, just because something is counterintuitive or even illogical doesn’t mean it’s incorrect. Physical behavior is often more bizarre than we’d ever expect, and that is why we must always confront our predictions with the harsh reality of experiments. Perhaps, contrary to what we’d intuitively expect, nature really did follow these Bohmian trajectories.

In 2006, physicists Yves Couder and Emmanuel Fort began to bounce an oil droplet atop a vibrating fluid bath made out of that same oil, recreating an analogue of the quantum double-slit experiment. As the wave ripples down the tank and approaches the two slits, the droplet bounces atop the waves and is guided through one slit or the other by the waves. When many droplets were passed through the slits and a statistical pattern emerged, it was found to exactly reproduce the standard predictions of quantum mechanics: the interference pattern that had been known since the time of Thomas Young.

In 2013, an expanded team led by John Bush at MIT leveraged the same technique to test a different quantum system: confining electrons into a circular corral-like area by a ring of ions. To the surprise of many, with an appropriately set up boundary, the underlying wave patterns that are produced are complex, but the trajectory of the bouncing droplets atop them actually follow a pattern determined by the wavelength of the waves, in agreement with the quantum predictions that underlie them.

This photo with a trajectory map atop it (white curve) shows surface waves that include a bouncing droplet which is confined in a circular area. The waves reflect back on one another from the boundary of the tank, producing ripples that steer the droplet in a non-random trajectory that possesses many of the same aspects inherent to quantum mechanics.
Credit: Dan Harris/MIT

What appeared to be random, in these experiments, wasn’t truly random at all, but rather provided a thrilling confirmation of the ideas of pilot wave theory.

Or so it seemed. What looked like it could be a shocking revelation, all of a sudden, all fell apart.

Normally, the double slit experiment only gives you the vaunted interference pattern if you don’t measure which of the two slits the particle passes through. At quantum scales, it’s possible to set up a detector at the site of the slits themselves, measuring which slit each particle goes through. If you do this, your experiment still works, but the interference pattern is destroyed by “forcing” that interaction. You simply wind up with two piles of particles on the other side, with each pile corresponding to particles that simply passed straight through one of the two slits, with no interference effects at all.

In Couder and Fort’s original 2006 experiment, they had set 75 separate bouncing droplets through the slits where they could watch which slit each droplet passed through — while also recording the pattern of where they landed on the screen — finding the needed interference pattern. If this held up, it would seem to confirm that, perhaps, there really could be these hidden variables underlying what appeared to be an indeterminate quantum reality.

And then the reproduction attempts came. Lo and behold, as soon as the path through one of the two slits was singled out by each droplet, the paths that the particle takes depart from what quantum mechanics predicts. There was no interference pattern, and it was found that the original work contained a few mistakes that were corrected in the reproduction attempt. As the eight authors of the 2015 study refuting Couder and Fort’s work (emphasis mine) conclude:

“We show that the ensuing particle-wave dynamics can capture some characteristics of quantum mechanics such as orbital quantization. However, the particle-wave dynamics can not reproduce quantum mechanics in general, and we show that the single-particle statistics for our model in a double-slit experiment with an additional splitter plate differs qualitatively from that of quantum mechanics.”

spookiness
A vibrating oil surface with a droplet bouncing upon it will appear to reproduce a number of aspects of quantum mechanics, but was shown to display subtle but measurable fundamental differences to the true quantum theory. The double-slit experiment, importantly, cannot be reproduced by this quantum analogue system, indicating that the analogy is flawed and limited.
Credit: A. Andersen et al., Phys. Rev. E, 2015

Of course, arguing over whether reality is:

  • truly acausal,
  • truly indeterminate,
  • or whether it truly lacks any type of hidden variables imaginable,

is tantamount to playing a never-ending game of whack-a-mole. Any specific claim that can be tested can always be ruled out, but it can be replaced with a more complex, hitherto untestable claim that still purports to have whatever aspects (or combination of aspects) one desires. Still, when assembling our picture of reality, it’s important to make sure that we don’t ideologically choose one that conflicts with the experiments we can perform, and that we accept reality as it is. It’s for these inescapable reasons that work on quantum entanglement, arguably the “spookiest” component of quantum physics, was awarded the 2022 Nobel Prize in physics.

We may not have the ultimate, complete, full answer to the question of how the Universe works, but we have knocked down a tremendous number of pretenders from the throne. If your predictions disagree with experiments, your theory is wrong, no matter how popular, compelling, or beautiful it happens to be. We have not yet ruled out all possible incarnations of Bohmian mechanics, or of more general pilot wave theories, or of all possible quantum mechanics interpretations that possess hidden variables. In fact, it may not ever be possible to do so. However, every attempt to construct a theory that agrees with experiment requires some level of quantum spookiness that simply cannot be done away with.

The least spooky alternative, as of 2015, has thoroughly been falsified, as a single, concrete, deterministic set of equations simply fails to describe the reality we observe and measure.

In this article
Sign up for the Starts With a Bang newsletter
Travel the universe with Dr. Ethan Siegel as he answers the biggest questions of all

Related

Up Next